Kurt Gödel |
Kurt Gödel
(1906-1978) was one of the most important mathematicians of the 20th century.
In 1931, when he was 25, he rose to fame with his mathematical proof that the attempt to
build a complete axiomatic system, from which one can deduce all the arithmetic
of natural numbers or any equivalent system, is doomed to failure.
His first
incompleteness theorem says the following:
Every consistent formal system as powerful as elementary
arithmetic is not complete (it contains true undecidable propositions).
Let us look at a
simplified informal demonstration:
Let theorem G say the following: This theorem G cannot be proved from the
axioms and rules of system S.
- If
we assume that Theorem G is false, system
S is inconsistent, since a false theorem can be proved from the
axioms and rules of S.
- Then
if S is consistent, G must be
true, and therefore cannot be proved from the axioms of S.
Gödel’s theorem
shows that every axiomatic
formalization of arithmetic is either inconsistent (it allows false
theorems to be proved), or incomplete
(it contains true theorems that cannot be proved).
David Hilbert |
The German
mathematician David Hilbert published a list of 23 outstanding pending problems
of mathematics. In the second place of his list he posed the following: Prove that the
axioms of arithmetic are consistent.
Gödel's second
incompleteness theorem says this:
Given a theory T, generated from basic arithmetic
axioms and formal rules of deduction, if T contains the proof of its own
consistency, then T is inconsistent.
In other words,
Gödel’s second theorem proves that the second Hilbert problem has no solution.
What did Kurt Gödel
think about the dilemma between realism and anti-realism? To verify that Gödel
was a Platonic realist, it is enough to look at this paragraph he wrote in a
supplement to his article What is Cantor's Continuum Problem?, initially
written in 1964:
Despite their
remoteness from sense experience, we do have something like a perception of the
objects of set theory, as is seen from the fact that the axioms force
themselves upon us as being true. I don’t see any reason why we should have
less confidence in this kind of perception, i.e., in mathematical intuition,
than in sense perception which induces us to build up physical theories, hoping
that the future perceptions of our senses will be of agreement with them.
Against this
assertion, anti-realists assert that, if
we cannot trust perception through the senses, because we are subject
(for instance) to optical illusions, we
cannot trust mathematical intuition either. However, as Gödel points
out, optical and other sensory illusions are not important enough to make us
doubt the coherence of the scientific theories that are based on our perceptions
and try to explain them. On the contrary, optical illusions have also been
detected, and scientific theories have been built to explain them. On the other
hand, unlike optical illusions, of which there are many examples, it is not so
common to find cases in which mathematical intuition leads us to error.
Therefore, according to Gödel, this criticism of the realistic position has no
force.
Other more weighty criticisms
were expressed by Rudolf Carnap in The Logical Syntax of Language (1934), such as
the following:
·
Mathematical intuition does not exist: it is just
made of agreements on the use of symbols.
·
Mathematical propositions are compatible with every
possible experience and are empty of content, therefore facts or mathematical
objects do not exist.
·
It is possible to make mathematics compatible with
strict empiricism, by asserting that the truths of mathematics are based only
on syntactic agreements, while empirical science is based on sensory
experience.
To these criticisms,
Gödel answers that the syntactic
conventions Carnap says support mathematics must be consistent. If they
are not, it would be possible to deduce from them any empirical affirmation
whatever. But the consistency tests should be either mathematical or empirical,
and in both cases his theorems of
incompleteness and other mathematical results wreck Carnap’s anti-realistic position.
Saint Anselm of Canterbury |
It is curious that
Kurt Gödel was the author of a
mathematical proof of the existence of God. It is a formulation in mathematical
terms of the
ontological argument by St. Anselm of Canterbury. The proof is unassailable,
but it is based on five axioms considered evident, and atheists just have to
deny one of those axioms to reject Gödel’s proof. And even if they cannot get
rid of them, they can always claim that this does not prove that they are true.
The same post in Spanish
Thematic Thread on Mathematics: Previous Next
Manuel Alfonseca
Very interesting. Thanks for this. I am having some difficulty -- I wonder if Carnap's syntactic conventions need to be consistent as a system or not, but I am thinking that your analysis is correct.
ReplyDeleteOf course my description of Carnap's and Gödel's arguments is schematic, as with the two incompleteness theorems. A more rigorous treatment would have been out-of-place.
Delete