The Cheshire cat, famous invisible cat |
In an
earlier post in this blog, I explained with an example the mode of
reasoning based on abduction. Although
not as strong as deduction and induction, abduction reaches high degrees of
confidence in fields such as history, art criticism and others, less scientific
than mathematics or natural science.
In another
post published in March 2016, I described the
fallacy of the invisible cat, which confuses a sufficient condition
with a necessary condition for something to happen. This situation occurs when
there are several possible causes that may have given rise to the same
phenomenon.
In some cases, if we apply abduction to a situation where the fallacy
of the invisible cat could occur, a conclusion can be reached. Think of the example
I proposed to describe this fallacy:
If there were an invisible cat on that table, we would see nothing.
We see nothing.
Therefore there is an invisible cat on that table.
This is a fallacy, because there are other reasons that can lead to the
same result (we see nothing on the table), apart from the presence of an
invisible cat. For example, we would also see nothing if there is nothing
on the table.
If we consider all the possible causes of a phenomenon, we’ll usually
find that they have different probabilities. In our example, what does the
reader think is the most likely cause for seeing nothing on the table? What is
the best explanation? That there is an invisible cat, or that there is nothing?
I think we all agree that the second is infinitely more probable than the
first. Well, if we choose that explanation, we are applying abductive
reasoning. That is why abduction is also called inference
to the best explanation, and also the no-miracles argument. The word miracle
is used here with the meaning that it would be a miracle if the correct
explanation was an invisible cat, for it is much less probable.
Witnesses of the miracle of the Sun, October 13 1917 |
In another
post in this blog I mentioned the miracle of Fatima, witnessed by 30,000 to
40,000 people. Two explanations can be given: a) something unusual happened; or
b) all these people suffered a collective hallucination
(something we don’t know that it exists). What is the most likely explanation
in this case? Surely an atheist won’t agree with me, but I think the first is the
most likely explanation. In other words, in this case, the no-miracles argument would lead us to conclude that there
really was a miracle. The argument would run in this way:
The explanation based
on a collective hallucination affecting tens of thousands of people is so
unlikely, that it would be a miracle if it were true, therefore it is more
logical to conclude that these people actually witnessed a miracle.
Hilary Putnam |
The American mathematician and philosopher Hilary Putnam uses this type
of arguments to justify his position, favorable to the philosophical theory
called realism of entities, within the framework of the
discussion about whether or not the entities posited by science really exist.
His reasoning can be summarized as follows:
The best explanation
of the success of science is the assertion that the entities whose existence is
postulated are real: atoms, electrons, genes, viruses, and so on. It is
extremely unlikely that science can be so successful in its technological
applications if all that should be false. We know that true conclusions can follow
from a false theory, but it would be a miracle if this had happened so many
times, and all those theories were false.
Let's see how Putnam says this in his book Meaning and the Moral
Sciences (1978):
[T]he modern positivist has to
leave it without explanation [the fact that] ‘electron-calculi’ and ‘space-time-calculi’
and ‘DNA-calculi’ correctly predict observable phenomena if, in reality, there are
no electrons, no space-time, no DNA molecules. If there are such things, then a
natural explanation of the success of these theories is that they are partially
true accounts of how they behave. And a natural account of the way in which
scientific theories succeed each other −say, the way in which Einstein's
Relativity succeeded Newton's Universal Gravitation− is that a partially
correct/partially incorrect account of a theoretical object −say the
gravitational field, or the metric structure of space-time, or both− is
replaced by a better account of the same object or objects. But if these
objects don’t really exist at all, then it is a miracle that a theory that
speaks of gravitational action at a distance successfully predicts phenomena; it
is a miracle that a theory that speaks of curved space-time successfully
predicts phenomena.
What
do anti-realists answer to this argument? Are they convinced? We’ll take a look
at this in the next post.The same post in Spanish
Thematic Thread on Philosophy and Logic: Previous Next
Manuel Alfonseca
No comments:
Post a Comment